What Did Darwin Do?

Darwin-chap-10

Origin of Species, Chap. 10

WHAT was it, exactly, that Charles Darwin achieved with his theory of evolution? It’s well beyond our abilities to describe the fullness of Darwin’s accomplishment, and we’ll probably regret attempting this essay, but we’ll give it our best. Please, dear reader, don’t think less of Darwin because of your Curmudgeon’s shortcomings.

Darwin began with information that was common knowledge. Some had been around for a few generations (like geology), and in some cases for centuries (the apparent relationships among various organisms), and in other cases from a time before history — improving our breeds of agricultural products and domesticated animals.

Darwin added more recent observations of how living things are distributed around the world. And then he did something that was extraordinarily original — he not only tied all of that information together into a comprehensive description of life on earth, but then he explained — using natural means only — how it all occurred.

Let’s consider some of the pre-existing ideas Darwin used.

1. Geology, pioneered by James Hutton, one of the great thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment. He first published his ideas in 1785, a quarter-century before Charles Darwin was born. Darwin probably couldn’t have made any sense of what he saw without an understanding of the geological processes that had altered the earth and the millions of years they required.

2. Visible patterns of physical similarities among living things — an idea that had been obvious for centuries. Carl Linnaeus published the system of Linnaean taxonomy more than a century before Darwin published Origin of Species. The Linnaeus system established a hierarchical structure of classification based upon observed physical characteristics. That system has been revised considerably since it was first proposed, but when today’s students are introduced to the biological classifications of kingdom, phylum, class, order, family, genus, and species, they are learning the basics of the Linnaeus system. He gave gave linguistic rigor to what thoughtful observers had noticed since the time of Aristotle.

3. Geographic patterns of relationships among living things. Regional wildlife descriptions had long been available, but what Darwin observed on a global scale was inconsistent with his expectations as a student of theology. The patterns that emerged from the evidence strongly suggested a history of natural dispersion rather than special creation, and in Origin of Species he dealt with this at length — it’s the only subject to which two specific chapters are devoted. For a sample, in Chapter 11, he wrote:

In considering the distribution of organic beings over the face of the globe, the first great fact which strikes us is, that neither the similarity nor the dissimilarity of the inhabitants of various regions can be accounted for by their climatal and other physical conditions. … There is hardly a climate or condition in the Old World which cannot be paralleled in the New at least as closely as the same species generally require; … yet these are not inhabited by a peculiar fauna or flora. Notwithstanding this parallelism in the conditions of the Old and New Worlds, how widely different are their living productions! [Emphasis supplied.]

A second great fact which strikes us in our general review is, that barriers of any kind, or obstacles to free migration, are related in a close and important manner to the differences between the productions of various regions. …

A third great fact, partly included in the foregoing statements, is the affinity of the productions of the same continent or sea, though the species themselves are distinct at different points and stations. … We see in these facts some deep organic bond, prevailing throughout space and time, over the same areas of land and water, and independent of their physical conditions. The naturalist must feel little curiosity, who is not led to inquire what this bond is.

This bond, on my theory, is simply inheritance, that cause which alone, as far as we positively know, produces organisms quite like, or, as we see in the case of varieties nearly like each other.

And in Chapter 12:

He who admits the doctrine of the creation of each separate species, will have to admit, that a sufficient number of the best adapted plants and animals have not been created on oceanic islands; for man has unintentionally stocked them from various sources far more fully and perfectly than has nature.

[…]

I have carefully searched the oldest voyages, but have not finished my search; as yet I have not found a single instance, free from doubt, of a terrestrial mammal (excluding domesticated animals kept by the natives) inhabiting an island situated above 300 miles from a continent or great continental island; and many islands situated at a much less distance are equally barren.

[…]

The most striking and important fact for us in regard to the inhabitants of islands, is their affinity to those of the nearest mainland, without being actually the same species.

[…]

The law which causes the inhabitants of an archipelago, though specifically distinct, to be closely allied to those of the nearest continent, we sometimes see displayed on a small scale, yet in a most interesting manner, within the limits of the same archipelago. Thus the several islands of the Galapagos Archipelago are tenanted, as I have elsewhere shown, in a quite marvellous manner, by very closely related species; so that the inhabitants of each separate island, though mostly distinct, are related in an incomparably closer degree to each other than to the inhabitants of any other part of the world.

[…]

The principle which determines the general character of the fauna and flora of oceanic islands, namely, that the inhabitants, when not identically the same, yet are plainly related to the inhabitants of that region whence colonists could most readily have been derived, the colonists having been subsequently modified and better fitted to their new homes, is of the widest application throughout nature.

4. Individual differences (Darwin’s term for what we call mutations) that are inherited. Darwin knew nothing of genetics, but he knew what all farmers and cattlemen knew. In Chapter 1 of Origin he wrote — note the ambiguous use of the word “race” which was common at the time:

Let us now briefly consider the steps by which domestic races have been produced, either from one or from several allied species. Some little effect may, perhaps, be attributed to the direct action of the external conditions of life, and some little to habit; but he would be a bold man who would account by such agencies for the differences of a dray and race horse, a greyhound and bloodhound, a carrier and tumbler pigeon. One of the most remarkable features in our domesticated races is that we see in them adaptation, not indeed to the animal’s or plant’s own good, but to man’s use or fancy. … We cannot suppose that all the breeds were suddenly produced as perfect and as useful as we now see them; indeed, in several cases, we know that this has not been their history. The key is man’s power of accumulative selection: nature gives successive variations; man adds them up in certain directions useful to him. In this sense he may be said to make for himself useful breeds.

And in Chapter 2 he wrote, with a hint of theory thrown in:

Again, we have many slight differences which may be called individual differences, such as are known frequently to appear in the offspring from the same parents, or which may be presumed to have thus arisen, from being frequently observed in the individuals of the same species inhabiting the same confined locality. No one supposes that all the individuals of the same species are cast in the very same mould. These individual differences are highly important for us, as they afford materials for natural selection to accumulate, in the same manner as man can accumulate in any given direction individual differences in his domesticated productions.

In Darwin’s final chapter of Origins, Chapter 14, he said:

Man does not actually produce variability; he only unintentionally exposes organic beings to new conditions of life, and then nature acts on the organisation, and causes variability. But man can and does select the variations given to him by nature, and thus accumulate them in any desired manner. He thus adapts animals and plants for his own benefit or pleasure. He may do this methodically, or he may do it unconsciously by preserving the individuals most useful to him at the time, without any thought of altering the breed. It is certain that he can largely influence the character of a breed by selecting, in each successive generation, individual differences so slight as to be quite inappreciable by an uneducated eye. This process of selection has been the great agency in the production of the most distinct and useful domestic breeds.

So Darwin had observed, collected, and described. He could see — as had others — the natural pattern of life’s diversity. Because of his travels and his widespread correspondence with other naturalists, perhaps he saw these things more clearly and comprehensively than any of his predecessors or contemporaries. He was obviously a splendid naturalist.

But up to that point he hadn’t addressed the great unknown — How had life’s diversity occurred? He knew that in a small way and over a brief span of time it could happen, as with human efforts in breeding varieties (or “races”) of dogs, horses, and pigeons. And he could see a worldwide geographical pattern to the diversity of life. He suspected that inheritance was at the root of it all. But what drove the system in nature? What was the cause of speciation?

Then he got his inspiration. Darwin credits Thomas Malthus for sparking his idea of natural selection. See his autobiographical notes: at page 83-84 (at that site, search for “Malthus”):

In October 1838, that is, fifteen months after I had begun my systematic enquiry, I happened to read for amusement ‘Malthus on Population,’ and being well prepared to appreciate the struggle for existence which everywhere goes on from long-continued observation of the habits of animals and plants, it at once struck me that under these circumstances favourable variations would tend to be preserved, and unfavourable ones to be destroyed. The result of this would be the formation of new species. Here then I had at last got a theory by which to work; but I was so anxious to avoid prejudice, that I determined not for some time to write even the briefest sketch of it.

Contrary to the assumption of creationists, Darwin didn’t begin with the theory of evolution in mind, hoping for evidence to support that idea. Rather, in proper scientific sequence, he first assembled all the evidence that was then available, observed that the global distribution of species didn’t support the concept of special creation, and only afterward did he conceive of natural selection as the explanation.

After a delay of 20 years, Darwin published Origin of Species. He summarized his evidence in Chapter 14, the book’s final chapter, which starts out saying:

As this whole volume is one long argument, it may be convenient to the reader to have the leading facts and inferences briefly recapitulated.

After reviewing much evidence, and rebutting many objections, he takes the well-known phenomenon of human-influenced domestic plant and animal breeding as a model, applies Malthusian dynamics, and says:

There is no obvious reason why the principles which have acted so efficiently under domestication should not have acted under nature. In the preservation of favoured individuals and races, during the constantly-recurrent Struggle for Existence, we see the most powerful and ever-acting means of selection. The struggle for existence inevitably follows from the high geometrical ratio of increase which is common to all organic beings. This high rate of increase is proved by calculation, by the effects of a succession of peculiar seasons, and by the results of naturalisation, as explained in the third chapter. More individuals are born than can possibly survive. A grain in the balance will determine which individual shall live and which shall die, — which variety or species shall increase in number, and which shall decrease, or finally become extinct. … The slightest advantage in one being, at any age or during any season, over those with which it comes into competition, or better adaptation in however slight a degree to the surrounding physical conditions, will turn the balance.

[…]

Man, though acting on external characters alone and often capriciously, can produce within a short period a great result by adding up mere individual differences in his domestic productions; and every one admits that there are at least individual differences in species under nature. …

If then we have under nature variability and a powerful agent always ready to act and select, why should we doubt that variations in any way useful to beings, under their excessively complex relations of life, would be preserved, accumulated, and inherited? Why, if man can by patience select variations most useful to himself, should nature fail in selecting variations useful, under changing conditions of life, to her living products? What limit can be put to this power, acting during long ages and rigidly scrutinising the whole constitution, structure, and habits of each creature, — favouring the good and rejecting the bad? I can see no limit to this power, in slowly and beautifully adapting each form to the most complex relations of life.

That’s all we can do in a brief essay. Darwin’s ideas seem familiar to us now, and the concept of natural selection seems almost obvious. But throughout human history, although much of the evidence was available, it wasn’t obvious at all. It required Charles Darwin to reason it out.

Copyright © 2009. The Sensuous Curmudgeon. All rights reserved.

add to del.icio.usAdd to Blinkslistadd to furlDigg itadd to ma.gnoliaStumble It!add to simpyseed the vineTailRankpost to facebook

. AddThis Social Bookmark Button . Permalink for this article

9 responses to “What Did Darwin Do?

  1. Bravo! I have only one tiny niggling remark:

    all of that information together into a comprehensive description of life on earth, but then he explained — using natural means only — how it all occurred.

    The important thing, it seems to me — a point that bears directly on “the Controversy” — is how we understand the importance of “natural means only.”

    Our antagonists like to construe this as an a priori, hence dogmatic, fixation on naturalism as a metaphysical commitment — one that they like to construe as a mere subjective preference that functions as a post hoc rationalization for our hedonism, paganism, etc.

    Better, I think, to head this objection off at the pass by insisting that “natural means only” implies only that the theory be testable , i.e. that intersubjective agreement about theories is constrained by available evidence garnered through observation and experimentation.

    Contra our antagonists, evolutionary theory is very much testable, in the sense that evolutionary theory makes quite specific predictions about what we should expect to see if it is true. And, of course, the content of those predictions changes as the theory is revised to accommodate new avenues of research and new discoveries.

  2. Carl Sachs says: “Better, I think, to head this objection off at the pass …”

    Hmmmm. I had thought that was inherent in the way Darwin went about it. The facts came first, and only then did he conceive the explanation. That’s the opposite of how creationists operate.

  3. So far as I understand, Darwin understood the facts he’d gathered to be what needed to be explained, but my point is that the explanation itself needs to be tested. ID proponents can explain pretty much anything by saying “the designer did it.” The explanation is uninteresting because it is vacuous, and it is vacuous because it is untestable.

  4. Carl Sachs says: “… but my point is that the explanation itself needs to be tested.”

    Understood. It is tested, constantly. Every fossil dug up is a test. The distribution of living creatures (if not artificially distorted by us) is a test. Every genome mapped is a test. Evolution is doing fine. There are no tests for ID.

  5. Popper put it this way: “the theory that explains everything explains nothing.”
    — meaning that an explanatory model that is consistent with all possible observational/experimental outcomes is, by definition, untestable (because no observation or experimental result can falsify it), and thus is no theory (in the scientific sense of the term) at all.

  6. Gabriel Hanna

    Generally, in physics, we define “real” things in terms of measurements.

    So, you have a clock, it goes tick-tick-tick, and then you say “Time is when you count ticks”. And if someone says, “Well, what happens is the clock ticks are getting slower and slower?” Our answer is, “Clock ticks DEFINE time.” One tick is one tick is one tick.

    So we don’t have the philosophical baggage of saying that only the natural world exists. You can say whatever you want about the supernatural, it can be real or not, but if youcan’t measure it it’s not “real” in the physics sense.

    So a lot of things we talk about, like potential energy, or electric fields, those things aren’t “real” in that sense.

    The electric field, for example, is what you have when you have only ONE charged object. But you can’t measure the field, without a SECOND charged object, which means you are measuring the FORCE, not the field. So why bother with the field? Well, one reason is that it seems odd to say that nothing is happening until a second charged object shows up. How does the first one “know” the second one is there so it can reach out and put a force on it? It’s a lot easier to deal with fields, or potentials which are even less “real”, if that’s possible.

    Not every physicist would agree with me here 100%, so don’t let me be too dogmatic.

  7. Carl Sachs: In response to your thoughtful prodding, I tweaked the paragraph that begins: “3. Geographic patterns of relationships among living things.” Now it’s more suggestive of Darwin’s thinking (at least as I understand it), and it explains why I quoted so much of Darwin’s writing on that issue. The “geographical dispersion” issue was a far bigger factor to Darwin than we generally appreciate.

    And I just added a new paragraph after the discussion of Malthus, pointing out that Darwin’s theory came only after the facts had been assembled.

  8. Very nice and complete article. What Darwin really accomplished was to provide a plausible explanation for evolution. Evolution had been proposed many times before Darwin, but no one presented the facts like him.